< < <
Date > > >
|
< < <
Thread > > >
Re: gender: Judith Butler's pseudo materialism and cultural feminism.
by md7148
19 March 2000 00:56 UTC
Gender oppression is not a construction. It is as real and oppressive
as capitalism. that is what Judith Butler does not seem to get, and that
is why she is so popular among the non-feminist males. Plus, I have not
read her criticizing sexist consequences of socio-biology at all. Thus, i
wonder what her relavancy to the issue at stake here.
However, many feminists criticize Butler. Mackinnon is one of them.
Marxist-feminists do not also agree with Judith Butler.
I still prefer Mackinnon's definition of gender instead of Butler's
definition of gender that valorizes women as a group.If we don't define
women as an oppressed group, then there is no point to talk about women's
emancipation or some form of equality between the sexes. Once the gender
category is fragmented, it becomes apoliticized. GENDER IS WHAT
FEMINISTS NEED JUST AS CLASS IS WHAT MARXISTS NEED. Since
inequalities are systemic and not simply constructed or discursively
redeemed, they should radically be changed. Butler's post-modernism
does not allow this possibility because her fragmented theory of power
turns against herself. She wants too much, but still achives too little. I
think McKinnons' definition of gender (sexuality) is
much clearer, more straightforward and convincing than Butler's:
" the molding direction, and expresion of sexuality organizes society into
two sexes: women and men. this division underlies the totality of social
realations.sexuality is the social process through social relations of
gender are created, organized, experessed, and directed, creating the
social beings we know as women and men,as their relations create society"
"women have seen unjustly unequal to men because of the social meaning of
their bodies. feminist theory is critical of GENDER as a determinant of
life chances, finding that it is women who differentialy suffer from the
distinction of sex.... to see existing relations between the sexes as a
social equality, rathern than based on inherent differences, si to reject
the judgement that those relations express whatever might validly or
immutably distinguish the sexes"
See for a critique of Judith Butler, post-modern feminism and cultural
relativism the collection of articles in _Materialist Femiminism_ ,edited
by Rosemary Hennessy...
Seee for a critique of Foucault Nancy Harstock's article about if
Foucault's theory of power is useful for women.
Morover, Foucault also made some sexist comments about women in the
past. His theory of power does NOT consider rape as a power relationship.
He thinks it is part of what constitutes sex, not even sexuality.
Has somebody noticed how Butler "exactly" defines gender below? I have not
seen any. it is just a language game. she does not even talk about
"oppression".
Mine
--
[from the introduction to Judith Butler's Bodies That Matter]
What I would propose in place of these conceptions of construction is
a return to the notion of matter, not as site or surface, but as a
process of materialization that stabilizes over time to produce the
effect of boundary, fixity, and surface we call matter. That matter
is always materialized has, I think, to be thought in relation to the
productive and, indeed, materializing effects of regulatory power in
the Foucaultian sense. Thus, the question is no longer, How is gender
constituted as and through a certain interpretation of sex? (a
question that leaves the "matter" of sex untheorized), but rather,
Through what regulatory norms is sex itself materialized? And how is
it that treating the materiality of sex as a given presupposes and
consolidates the normative conditions of its own emergence?
Crucially, then, construction is neither a single act nor a causal
process initiated by a subject and culminating in a set of fixed
effects. Construction not only takes place in time, but is itself a
temporal process which operates through the reiteration of norms; sex
is both produced and destabilized in the course of this reiteration.
As a sedimented effect of a reiterative or ritual practice, sex
acquires its naturalized effect, and, yet, it is also by virtue of
this reiteration that gaps and fissures are opened up as the
constitutive instabilities in such constructions, as that which
escapes or exceeds the norm, as that which cannot be wholly defined
or fixed by the repetitive labor of that norm. This instability is
the deconstituting possibility in the very process of repetition, the
power that undoes the very effects by which "sex" is stabilized, the
possibility to put the consolidation of the norms of "sex" into a
potentially productive crisis.
Certain formulations of the radical constructivist position appear
almost compulsively to produce a moment of recurrent exasperation,
for it seems that when the constructivist is construed as a
linguistic idealist, the constructivist refutes the reality of
bodies, the relevance of science, the alleged facts of birth, aging,
illness, and death. The critic might also suspect the constructivist
of a certain somatophobia and seek assurances that this abstracted
theorist will admit that there are, minimally, sexually
differentiated parts, activities, capacities, hormonal and
chromosomal differences that can be conceded without reference to
"construction." Although at this moment I want to offer an absolute
reassurance to my interlocutor, some anxiety prevails. To "concede"
the undeniability of "sex" or its "materiality" is always to concede
some version of "sex," some formation of "materiality." Is the
discourse in and through which that concession occurs-and, yes, that
concession invariably does occur-not itself formative of the very
phenomenon that it concedes? To claim that discourse is formative is
not to claim that it originates, causes, or exhaustively composes
that which it concedes; rather, it is to claim that there is no
reference to a pure body which is not at the same time a further
formation of that body. In this sense, the linguistic capacity to
refer to sexed bodies is not denied, but the very meaning of
"referentiality" is altered. In philosophical terms, the constative
claim is always to some degree performative.
In relation to sex, then, if one concedes the materiality of sex or
of the body, does that very conceding operate - performatively - to
materialize that sex? And further, how is it that the reiterated
concession of that sex - one which need not take place in speech or
writing but might be "signaled" in a much more inchoate way -
constitutes the sedimentation and production of that material effect?
The moderate critic might concede that some part of "sex" is
constructed, but some other is certainly not, and then, of course,
find him or herself not only under some obligation to draw the line
between what is and is not constructed, but to explain how it is that
"sex" comes in parts whose differentiation is not a matter of
construction. But as that line of demarcation between such ostensible
parts gets drawn, the "unconstructed" becomes bounded once again
through a signifying practice, and the very boundary which is meant
to protect some part of sex from the taint of constructivism is now
defined by the anti-constructivist's own construction. Is
construction something which happens to a ready-made object, a
pregiven thing, and does it happen in degrees? Or are we perhaps
referring on both sides of the debate to an inevitable practice of
signification, of demarcating and delimiting that to which we then
"refer," such that our "references" always presuppose-and often
conceal-this prior delimitation? Indeed, to "refer" naively or
directly to such an extra-discursive object will always require the
prior delimitation of the extra-discursive. And insofar as the
extra-discursive is delimited, it is formed by the very discourse
from which it seeks to free itself. This delimitation, which often is
enacted as an untheorized presupposition in any act of description,
marks a boundary that includes and excludes, that decides, as it
were, what will and will not be the stuff of the object to which we
then refer. This marking off will have some normative force and,
indeed, some violence, for it can construct only through erasing; it
can bound a thing only through enforcing a certain criterion, a
principle of selectivity.
What will and will not be included within the boundaries of "sex"
will be set by a more or less tacit operation of exclusion. If we
call into question the fixity of the structuralist law that divides
and bounds the "sexes" by virtue of their dyadic differentiation
within the heterosexual matrix, it will be from the exterior regions
of that boundary (not from a "Position," but from the discursive
possibilities opened up by the constitutive outside of hegemonic
positions), and it will constitute the disruptive return of the
excluded from within the very logic of the heterosexual symbolic.
The trajectory of this text, then, will pursue the possibility of
such disruption, but proceed indirectly by responding to two
interrelated questions that have been posed to constructivist
accounts of gender, not to defend constructivism per se, but to
interrogate the erasures and exclusions that constitute its limits.
These criticisms presuppose a set of metaphysical oppositions between
materialism and idealism embedded in received grammar which, I will
argue, are critically redefined by a poststructuralist rewriting of
discursive performativity as it operates in the materialization of
sex.
< < <
Date > > >
|
< < <
Thread > > >
|
Home